43 pages • 1 hour read
George BerkeleyA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Background
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
On the third day, it is immediately evident that Hylas has descended into full-blown skepticism. He argues essentially that nothing can ever be proven, that there will always be limitations to human knowledge, and that because of this, nothing can be said to actually exist. When Philonous points out that he knows he is standing on a rock, Hylas takes exception to the use of the word “know” and further argues that nothing can be fully known in the exact sense of the word.
Philonous, who to this point has made the argument that matter does not exist outside the mind that perceives it, now makes the surprising claim that this is no cause for skepticism. He contends that because his mind perceives objects in the world, these objects are real. Hylas again engages with Philonous on the topic of whether sensible things are real or perceived. The crisis of faith Hylas is experiencing stems from his inability to dispense with this distinction between reality and perception: For Hylas, to be real means to exist outside the mind; therefore if nothing exists outside the mind (as Philonous has convinced him) then nothing is real. Philonous himself has no such difficulty. He maintains that perception is what creates the existence of objects. Philonous also contends that Hylas’s descent into full skepticism, in which he argues despairingly that nothing can fully be known, is due to his insistence that matter exists outside the mind. He says to Hylas, “This makes you dream of those unknown natures in everything” (62-63), and he sees folly in such a perspective, especially compared to his own empirical view of how knowledge is acquired, namely through sensory perception.
Hylas requests to interrogate Philonous so that the latter must now defend his positions against critique. Hylas believes that his line of questioning will lead Philonous into the same kind of skepticism he finds himself in currently. Hylas begins by asking Philonous if the existence of things will survive the event of his death. Philonous assumes that things will still exist because there will be minds to perceive them, in addition to the mind of God that perceives all. Hylas tries a different attack, pointing out that according to his own admission, Philonous cannot empirically prove the mind of God, yet he still accepts that God perceives all things. He then asks why that same logic cannot apply to Hylas’s insistence that matter exists independently. Philonous counters that because his soul is able to produce ideas, and those ideas must come from somewhere, the idea of God is proof that God exists, whereas for matter, the same application of logic will not work. The difference is that the soul or spirit produces the notion of God. Philonous says that only a spirit knows and perceives ideas, and that matter does not have this ability.
Hylas tries to attack the argument by bringing up dreams, asking, “[W]hat difference is there between real things, and chimeras formed by the imagination, or the visions of a dream, since they are all equally in the mind?” (68). Philonous counters by saying that the clarity of thoughts formed by the imagination is weak, unlike the crispness of the image that forms from direct sensory perception. Hylas transitions back to the nature of God. He points out that attributing all ideas to God means that God is ultimately responsible for murder and sin. Philonous disputes this, claiming that sin is not defined by an outward physical act but by the “internal deviation from the laws of nature” (70). Hylas then tries to argue that if the two of them were to go around asking regular people whether matter exists, the average person would conclude that it does, and that Philonous’s views thus contradict common sense. Hylas then turns to the question of faulty perceptions, such as the appearance of a straight oar in the water looking bent. Philonous counters that seeing the bent oar is not a mistake of the immediate sense perception but is one of inference. He uses the analogy of the Copernican system as a means of explaining his point. The Earth spins and revolves around the sun, but since we do not feel that motion while on earth, we correctly conclude that there is no motion. However, removed from the Earth and seeing it from a distance, if we still hold that the Earth does not move, then we make a mistake in inference.
Hylas asks whether Philonous ever believed that matter existed independently of the mind, to which Philonous answers yes, but because of superficial examination of it. Hylas proceeds on a different course, attempting to poke holes in Philonous’s notion by pointing out that since God perceives all things, he likewise allows sin to happen. Philonous objects to this, insisting that sin is internal in the individual and is not an outward physical act.
Hylas continues his attack against Philonous’s position, insisting that by denying the existence of matter independent of the mind, Philonous is denying its reality, to which Philonous retreats to his primary position that matter is only real as far as it can be perceived. It has no absolute existence apart from perception. Hylas continues to try to argue against the premise again and again. Hylas asks, “Doth it not therefore follow from your principles, that no two can see the same thing?” (80). Hylas views this idea as absurd, yet Philonous disagrees. If Hylas is using the word “same” as philosophers typically use it—to signify an “abstract notion of identity” (80), then it is not absurd to think that it is possible for a group of people to see the same thing. This leads to an argument about the nature of language, as Hylas accuses Philonous of twisting language to fit his argument.
Hylas returns to the theological implications of immaterialism. He brings up creation and the book of Genesis, noting that the Earth, moon, stars and the like were created before mankind; this must mean that these things exist outside the mind. Philonous disagrees and explains why immaterialism aligns with the biblical history of creation. He rests his argument on the dichotomy between finite spirits, which exist in time, and God, who does not.
As this section of the text nears its conclusion, Hylas finally uses up all possible objections to Philonous’s argument, yet he is still somewhat reluctant to fully embrace Philonous’s idealist view. Philonous suggests that this may be in part due to deeply rooted biases in favor of materialism, an assertion with which Hylas agrees. As a sort of compromise, Hylas assents to Philonous’s view and accepts that his friend is correct; however, as a condition, Hylas insists on reframing the word matter in order to make better sense of the position. He redefines the word to mean “some sensible thing, whose existence consists in being perceived” (93), which better allows him to accept Philonous’s claims. Finally, as the dialogue concludes, Philonous describes a metaphor of a water fountain in which the water sprays upward to a point only to be pushed back down by gravity. This metaphor serves as an illustration of skepticism.
As Dialogue 3 begins, Hylas has apparently turned fully skeptical in his beliefs about knowledge, and this change appears to have occasioned something of an emotional crisis. Claiming that nothing can ever truly be known, he says, “We keep a stir about knowledge, and spend our lives in the pursuit of it, when, alas! we know nothing all the while: nor do I think it possible for us ever to know anything in this life” (61). This is a significant moment in the text, as it completes Philonous’s project of proving to Hylas that materialism leads to skepticism. This highlights one of the text’s central themes: The Critique of Materialism and the Defense of Idealism. As a point of reference, it is worth remembering that Hylas leveled the claim of skepticism against Philonous at the outset of the first dialogue.
The source of Hylas’s newfound skepticism lies in his inability to fully comprehend Philonous’s primary point. For his part, Philonous immediately shoots down Hylas’s notion that nothing can ever truly be known. To begin with, he bluntly asks Hylas, “Do I not know this to be a real stone that I stand on, and that which I see before my eyes to be a real tree?” (61). Hylas argues that there is no way for Philonous to affirm the existence of these objects—precisely the unreasonably skeptical position he accused Philonous of taking at the beginning. Philonous, however, makes a subtle but important correction to Hylas’s understanding of his thought: He asserts that because he perceives these objects, they do in fact exist. This is the significant distinction between Hylas’s new skepticism (which verges frighteningly on nihilism) and Philonous’s idealism. Philonous does not argue that nothing exists; instead, he relies on the empirical observation of sense to prove that something exists. There is no absolute material existence to the sensible object, meaning that these objects cannot exist unless they are perceived. Perception is what makes them real.
Later in this section of the dialogue, Philonous says:
I am of a vulgar cast, simple enough to believe my senses, and leave things as I find them. To be plain, it is my opinion, that the real things are those very things I see and feel, and perceive by my senses. These I know, and finding they answer all the necessities and purposes of life, have no reason to be solicitous about any other unknown beings (63).
Like his ancient predecessor Socrates, Philonous casts himself as a simple person, one who sides with the common view and rejects obscurantism. In this case, the common view can essentially be distilled to “seeing is believing.” This is not the same as denying that anything exists at all, as Hylas finds himself doing in this part of the dialogue.
Also evident in this disagreement is the theme of The Nature of Existence and the Role of Perception. In Philonous’s view, perception is what provides grounds for existence, rather than some unknown entity such as a substratum. Hylas’s continued reliance on the concept of the substratum leads him deeper into despair:
How often must I tell you, that I know not the real nature of any one thing in the universe? I may indeed upon occasion make use of pen, ink, and paper. But what any one of them is in its own true nature, I declare positively I know not. And the same is true with regard to every other corporeal thing. And, what is more, we are not only ignorant of the true and real nature of things, but even of their existence (62).
Hylas could accept that the essence of things was hidden from him so long as he felt sure that the things themselves existed. Now, deprived of even this most basic certainty, he feels he knows nothing at all and never can. He still fails to understand Philonous’s argument: There are no hidden essences; things exist exactly as (and because) we perceive them. Philonous chides Hylas for adopting such an extreme position, saying, “[I]s it not evident you are led into all these extravagancies by the belief of material substance?” (62). Here, he is directly correlating Hylas’s growing skepticism with his insistence on material substance.
Rhetorically, this dialogue differs slightly from the previous two in that Hylas takes on the role of questioner. He has come prepared for this third conversation with a litany of questions meant to discover some hole in Philonous’s logic. For example, he poses a hypothetical scenario, asking Philonous what would become of matter if he were to die. Philonous answers that so long as there are others who perceive matter, then it will exist. Hylas also employs the logical fallacy known as argumentum ad populum to persuade Philonous, suggesting that if he were to ask many others if matter exists, almost all of them would conclude that it does. Philonous argues vehemently against this position, as he does in each instance of Hylas new lines of questioning. In this way, the third dialogue is less interested in defining idealism (a task achieved in the previous dialogues) and more in defending it.
The Theological Implications of Idealism are also central in Dialogue 3. Philonous draws clear distinctions between materialism and idealism and the impact each has on theology:
For allowing it to be a thing possible and conceivable, that the corporeal world should have an absolute subsistence extrinsical to the mind of God, as well as to the minds of all created spirits: yet how could this set forth either the immensity or omniscience of the Deity, or the necessary and immediate dependence of all things on him? (86).
This is the book’s clearest statement of Berkeley’s core objection to materialism: Because materialism insists on the existence of matter independent from the mind (including the mind of God) it effectively argues that God is not omniscient. Berkeley sees this as a gateway to atheism, and he uses the character of Hylas to illustrate what he sees as the intellectual, spiritual, and emotional consequences of allowing human reason to usurp the place of God.
By George Berkeley