logo

43 pages 1 hour read

George Berkeley

Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1713

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Dialogue 2Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Dialogue 2 Summary

Hylas meets Philonous the next morning, and the conversation picks up where the two left off. Hylas mentions that he has been dwelling on the previous day’s conversation and wrestling with many of the concepts Philonous raised. Hylas thinks he has discovered a possible way of refuting Philonous and discusses what the science of the day understood about the brain and the rest of the central nervous system—that the brain is the source of sensations caused by external objects. Philonous disputes Hylas’s apparently scientific analysis. Philonous argues that the brain conceives of itself as a brain. Since it cannot be directly experienced through the senses, the brain is an idea like any other idea. After Philonous pushes back against Hylas, the latter is now at a complete loss for further rebuttal. Hylas concedes that Philonous has proven him a skeptic; however, he also insists that Philonous is likewise a skeptic. Philonous again insists that he is not a skeptic. He repeats his claim that objects only exist inside the mind that perceives them, yet they do exist. The materialist contention that objects exist outside the mind, in Philonous’s view, is actually a denial that they exist at all.

Philonous pivots to a more robust explanation of idealism, specifically that since humans are not in full command of our immediate sensory experiences, there must be a source for these. Because sensory experience happens involuntarily, Philonous argues that it must be the result of some higher order of being, namely God. He says, “As sure therefore as the sensible world really exists, so sure is there an infinite omnipresent spirit who contains and supports it” (46-47). Philonous argues that one’s sensory experiences are ideas in the mind of God. He contends that this is not a description of a passive God found in the things of the material world—the view he accuses Hylas and other materialists of taking. Hylas asks Philonous, “[A]re not you too of opinion that we see all things in God?” (49). Here, Philonous distinguishes his view from a prevailing sentiment of the time. After a lengthy explanation of how his view differs, Philonous sums it up by stating, “[T]here is a mind which affects me every moment with all the sensible impressions I perceive” (50). This, he points out, is not the same as seeing God in all things.

Hylas does not fully concede this point, instead stating that even if Philonous’s view of God is accepted, there may yet be cause to believe in a “third nature” in addition to those of spirits and ideas.

Philonous again returns to his main argument that nothing exists outside of the mind that perceives it. He asks Hylas to defend his belief in matter again. Hylas contends that he cannot ascertain any cause for his ideas other than matter and must therefore conclude that matter is the source of ideas. Philonous turns to semantics, re-establishing the common definition of matter before posing to Hylas the same question regarding the existence of matter: Can it exist without a mind that perceives it? Hylas does not dispute the argument that God is the source of all things, ideas included, but “that subordinate to the supreme agent there is a cause of a limited and inferior nature, which concurs in the production of our ideas” (51). Philonous turns the conversation to primary properties once again, this time centering on motion. Philonous argues that motion must be perceived in order to exist. Hylas finally concludes that matter is the instrument subordinate to God “in the production of our ideas” (52). After Philonous pokes holes in this assertion, Hylas becomes agitated and accuses Philonous of teasing him for his position.

Philonous argues that because we perceive things involuntarily, volition is not an immediate cause of perception. He suggests that the reason we have immediate perceptions is because God is the instrument that makes it happen. Hylas concedes that matter is not the instrument that causes ideas (as he previously claimed) before moving on to assert that matter is an occasion that Hylas defines as “an inactive unthinking being, at the presence whereof God excites ideas in our minds” (54). Hylas also acknowledges when pressed that he cannot define what he means when he says, “inactive unthinking being” (54). Hylas continues, stating that because there is a consistency to the occasions of matter, this should prove that it exists outside the mind. Philonous dismantles this position by pointing out that an omniscient, rational God would create this patterned consistency. He also contends that Hylas is using reason to postulate these positions, proving once again, at least by his evaluation, that matter cannot be empirically proven to exist. Any claim that matter does exist must rely on inference rather than on immediate perception.

Philonous offers a brief summation of the argument to this point, once again forcing Hylas to define what he thinks matter really is. Hylas now claims that matter consists of something unknown—a definition Philonous rejects as pure abstraction. When he asks Hylas where this “something unknown” exists, Hylas recognizes the trap (“something unknown” can exist only in the mind) and refuses to answer.

The two continue to argue about the existence of matter. Hylas finally states that because Philonous cannot prove that the existence of matter is impossible, holding to the fact of its existence in the manner Hylas is doing is an acceptable position. Philonous vehemently disputes this until finally Hylas states, “I acknowledge you have proved that matter is impossible; nor do I see what more can be said in defense of it. But at the same time that I give up this, I suspect all my other notions” (60). While conceding a large measure to Philonous, he has yet to give up the position that matter does indeed exist, and he requests one more conversation to take place the following day.

Dialogue 2 Analysis

At the outset of this dialogue, Hylas’s explanation of the soul reflects the tension between religious and scientific worldviews that defined his era:

It is supposed the soul makes her residence in some part of the brain, from which the nerves take their rise, and are thence extended to all parts of the body: and that outward objects, by the different impressions they make on the organs of sense, communicate certain vibrative motions to the nerves (43-44).

In this anatomy, the soul occupies the center of the nervous system and thus acts as the center of perception. Hylas argues in favor of the existence of mind-independent objects by claiming that if they did not exist, our brains would not be able to perceive them. The objects impress upon our brains and cause a sensory response. Philonous shoots down this proposition by pointing out that the brain is itself an object: “The brain therefore you speak of, being a sensible thing, exists only in the mind” (44). If the brain (or the soul, with its seat in the brain) is a passive receiver of sense impressions from the outside world, Philonous asks how it conceives an impression of itself. This form of interrogation—derived from Plato’s transcriptions of Socratic dialogues—is characteristic of Philonous’s argumentative style throughout. Through carefully selected questions, he leads Hylas to gradually dismantle his own arguments.

This second dialogue begins to explore The Theological Implications of Idealism more directly. As Philonous continues to attack Hylas’s understanding of the brain, he says, “Now, I would fain know whether you think it reasonable to suppose, that one idea or thing existing in the mind, occasions all other ideas. And if you think so, pray how do you account for the origin of that primary idea or brain itself?” (44). In Philonous’s view, this primary origin is God. He reiterates his position that “the sensible world is that which we perceive by our several senses; and that nothing is perceived by the senses beside ideas; and that no idea or archetype of an idea can exist otherwise than in a mind” (47). The linchpin of this whole philosophy, without which it falls apart, is the mind of God, which perceives all things even when no human mind perceives them. Of the sensible world, Philonous states:

I conclude, not that they have no real existence, but that seeing they depend not on my thought, and have an existence distinct from being perceived by me, there must be some other mind wherein they exist. As sure therefore as the sensible world really exists, so sure is there an infinite omnipresent spirit who contains and supports it (46-47).

The sensible world that we experience can only have its source through God. Philonous’s primary purpose here is to trace humanity’s ideas to a wellspring. Our sensory perceptions of objects in the world are not caused by the objects themselves. Instead, these are a result of God’s perceptions.

In Berkeley’s view, atheism is a natural consequence of materialism because it suggests that there is a physical world independent of mind. The apparent independence of this material world can lead us to conclude that it is likewise independent of God. Berkeley’s intention here is to disentangle the existence of matter from the belief in God. Philonous says, “But how can any idea or sensation exist in, or be produced by, anything but a mind or spirit?” (49). Here, he again denies the existence of the material world by reiterating that all sensible objects are in fact ideas perceived by a mind. There are not things in the physical sense, only ideas of things. Philonous continues along this line, stating, “the things by me perceived are known by the understanding, and produced by the will, of an infinite spirit” (50). Here, the things he perceives, his ideas, he attributes to the will of God.

Lastly, throughout much of this dialogue, Hylas still holds to his original idea that matter does exist in the world independent of perception, though with each new attempt at disproving Philonous, he veers closer to skepticism. Philonous summarizes Hylas’s attempts thus: “[A]t first, from a belief of material substance you would have it that the immediate objects existed without the mind; then that their archetypes; then causes; next instruments; then occasions: lastly, something in general, which being interpreted proves nothing” (57). For his part, Hylas insists “that our not being able to conceive a thing, is no argument against its existence” (57) and that “[t]he reality of things cannot be maintained without supposing the existence of matter” (58). Even though he is seemingly resolute in his insistence, his only recourse is to hold a weak position that ostensibly claims that Philonous cannot disprove that matter does exist. While all of Philonous’s arguments support his position that it does not absolutely exist, Hylas still maintains that it must, though his doubt is growing. In so doing, he adopts the position of the skeptic, the exact charge with which he labeled Philonous at the beginning of the previous dialogue.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text