logo

74 pages 2 hours read

Carole Pateman

The Sexual Contract

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1988

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Preface-Chapter 2Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Preface Summary

There has been a revival of interest in contract theory since the 1970s. Contract theorists emphasize conjectural histories about the original contract as well as interpretations of major political institutions, giving their attention to social and employment contracts. Pateman argues that not only do these dominant interpretations misrepresent social and employment contracts, but that they typically ignore the marriage contract altogether. This absence, she suggests, indicates the repression of the sexual contract in both contract theory and the original agreement. Thus, the failure of contract theory interpretations to acknowledge the roles and obligations of women within civil society obscures the contractual character of modern patriarchy. Furthermore, feminists and socialists are implicated in this failure.

Chapter 1 Summary: “Contracting In”

Stories, understood as conjectural histories, are how humans make sense of themselves and their social world, and one such story is that the authority and legitimacy of state and civil law and government originated in a contract. The original contract is a social-sexual contract, but the repression of the sexual contract obscures that the new civil society created through the original contract is a patriarchal social order. That is, political right is patriarchal right: the right of men to exercise power over women and to enjoy sexual access to women. 

There are two major reasons that contract theorists miss the sexual contract in their interpretations of the original contract and of major political institutions. One is through their literal interpretation of patriarchy as paternal rule. The second reason is that conventional approaches to the classic texts give a misleading picture of the distinctive features of civil society. These approaches emphasize the public sphere as politically relevant while seeing the private sphere as politically irrelevant. This public/private split is points to the natural/civil split described by classical contract theorists. 

By examining present-day institutions in Britain, Australia, and the US through the lens of the sexual contract, Pateman aims to demonstrate the patriarchal character of these institutions and societies that are maintained through contract. In particular, she is concerned with contract as a principle of social association and the subject of all contracts as “the property that individuals are held in their own persons” (5). Patriarchal domination becomes clearer when the sexual contract is retrieved from obscurity, as the sexual contract is the mechanism by which men transform their “natural” right over women into the security of civil patriarchal right, based on a belief in “natural” sexual difference. 

While proponents of contract have emphasized that the original contract and subsequent actual contracts secure universal individual freedom, Pateman points out that contract generates relations of domination and subordination. Meanwhile, some critics of contract, namely socialists, tend to focus on exploitation and inequality rather than subordination. Furthermore, in the liberal/socialist debate, their divergences over private enterprise and public state rest on the same patriarchal assumption of a private/natural and public/civil split and the irrelevancy of such a split to politics. Other critical interpretations of contract, like those coming from the feminist movement, have interpreted the very meaning of patriarchy in patriarchal terms and emphasized feminist demands in contractual terms. In short, what liberal, socialist, and feminist interpretations all overlook is the intersection of patriarchy, contract, socialism, and feminism.

The sexual contract, then, sheds light on how both proponents and critics of contract operate within the parameters of patriarchy: The notion of sexual difference as political difference is central to civil society, and this notion of difference has structured major social institutions. In addition, the idea of the sexual contract illuminates the character of different-sex relationships, in which men have, through the protection of the state, secured the right of sexual access to and command over women’s bodies.

Chapter 2 Summary: “Patriarchal Confusions”

Pateman discusses interpretations of “patriarchy” and the consequences of those interpretations. While the conjectural history about the original contract provides the origin of modern patriarchy, Pateman argues that there has been insufficient examination of patriarchy as a form of political power. Reasons for this absence include confusion over the meaning of “patriarchy” and the interpretations being themselves patriarchal. There have been three great periods of debate about patriarchy: the first in the 17th century, the second from 1861 into the 20th century, and the third beginning in the 1960s with the revival of organized feminism

The first period of debate was between patriarchalists and social contract theorists, with their leading figures being Filmer and Locke, respectively. To adequately interpret the debate and understand the development of modern patriarchy in social contract theory, the assumptions and interpretations underpinning the term “patriarchy” require examination. The three assumptions are the literal meaning of patriarchy as father-right, that patriarchal relations are familial relations, and that patriarchy is a universal feature of human society. The three lines of patriarchal political interpretation in this period of debate are the traditional view, which likens power relations to paternal rule; the classic view, which claims that political rule and paternal rule are identical; and the modern view, which makes patriarchy fraternal and contractual as it structures capitalist civil society. 

The second period of debate emerged with the publication of two significant books—Ancient Law by Sir Henry Maine and Mother Right by Johann Bachofen. The debate centered around the origins of the patriarchal family and/or civilization. The interpretation of patriarchy as paternal right imposes a problem here because it bypasses the original marriage contract, and therefore the relation between men and women and the idea of masculine sex-right. Interpretations of patriarchy in the 1980s come out of the third great period of debate. Gerda Lerner’s The Creation of Patriarchy is a prime example. Lerner’s line of thought (like other feminist thought of the time) is that patriarchy is universal, ahistorical, and fixed; she also uses its literal interpretation as father-right.

For Pateman, patriarchy must be disentangled from this fixity and paternalism to understand how contract theory created modern patriarchy. The anti-paternalism advocated by contract theory appears to make contract anti-patriarchal. However, such a view depends on the literal interpretation of patriarchy as father-right, as well as the repression of the sexual contract and conjugal right. The focus on familial relations obscures critical questions about relations between men and women, so feminist arguments focused on motherhood and fatherhood arise that miss the patriarchal construction of sexual difference as political difference. For Pateman, it is not paternalism that distinguishes modern patriarchy, but rather that in civil society, men as a fraternity generate political life and political right. 

Preface-Chapter 2 Analysis

Pateman published The Sexual Contract in the waning days of second wave feminism: a loosely defined movement that began in the 1960s and focused on a range of issues, including reproductive rights and employment outside the home. Second wave feminism comprised a variety of perspectives and approaches, with Pateman coming out of the radical tradition specifically. Though itself diverse, radical feminism generally seeks to uncover and dismantle the root causes of women’s oppression, which it locates in patriarchy rather than, for example, in class (as a Marxist feminist might). However, with its focus on systemic injustice and the politics of even the personal, radical feminism perhaps diverges most from liberal feminism, which critiques women’s oppression from within the Western liberal tradition, emphasizing women’s claim to individual autonomy and equality before the law. This liberal tradition is precisely what Pateman critiques in The Sexual Contract.

In the beginning chapters, Pateman explains the inadequacy of dominant interpretations of contract and patriarchy. By pointing out that contract creates relations of domination and subordination (as opposed to securing freedom) and that modern patriarchy is fraternal rather than paternal, she argues that contract creates and secures modern patriarchy. The relationship between contract and modern patriarchy can only be understood when the sexual contract, an integral half of the original contract, is retrieved from obscurity. This is because the sexual contract tells the story of the construction of sexual difference that permeates and intertwines private and public spheres. The beginning examination of the assumptions underlying interpretations of contract sets the stage for Pateman’s later analysis of contracts in both spheres. 

In the preface, Pateman makes the crucial claim that “The sexual contract is a repressed dimension of contract theory, an integral part of the rational choice of the familiar, original agreement” (ix). This claim requires an explanation of what the original contract is and how dominant analyses present it. Thus, in Chapter 1, Pateman writes that the original contract stories, conjectural histories attempting to explain the social world, provide “[a]n explanation for the binding authority of the state and civil law, and for the legitimacy of modern government [. . .] by treating our society as if it had originated in a contract” (1). She also explains how the original contract is presented, noting that while the original contract is a social-sexual contract, many interpretations emphasize the social aspect while ignoring the sexual aspect (1). The emphasis on the social aspect frames the story as one of freedom, based on two qualifying factors: one, that the original contract entails the exchange of the insecurities of natural freedom for the equality-based, civil freedom protected by the state; and two, that the original contract also entails the replacement of paternal rule with civil government as proper political right (1). For example, Rousseau claims that “the social contract enables individuals voluntarily to subject themselves to the state and civil law” (7), and Sir Henry Maine presents the creation of modern civil society as the movement from the old world of status, i.e., literal patriarchal father-right, to the new world of contract (9). Pateman is not disputing that these claims are integral to the original contract story. Instead, she is arguing that when the sexual contract is brought into view, the meanings of “civil,” “freedom,” and “contract” and the question of whose freedom is protected by the civil state become clearer.

Without the sexual contract story, it is easy for the supposed freedom granted by contract to appear universal and factual. Pateman writes:

The genius of contract theorists has been to present both the original contract and actual contracts as exemplifying and securing individual freedom. On the contrary, in contract theory universal freedom is always a hypothesis, a story, a political fiction. Contract always generates political right in the form of relations of domination and subordination (8). 

The “relations of domination and subordination” noted here rest on the notion of patriarchal right (8), but the character of this patriarchy is missed in dominant interpretations of contract theory. As Pateman notes at the beginning of Chapter 2:

‘Patriarchy’ refers to a form of political power, but although political theorists spend a great deal of time arguing about the legitimacy and justification of forms of political power, the patriarchal form has been largely ignored in the twentieth century. The standard interpretation of the history of modern political thought is that patriarchal theory and patriarchal right were dead and buried three hundred years ago (19).

The misunderstanding about patriarchy arises from several assumptions that Pateman points out in both Chapters 1 and 2. The main assumption is the literal interpretation of “patriarchy” as father-right or paternal rule. In Chapter 1, Pateman notes that the debate between Sir Robert Filmer, a proponent of patriarchy in the literal sense of the word as political right, and John Locke, who “insisted that paternal and political power were not the same and that contract was the genesis of political right” (3), allows Locke and his fellow contract theorists to appear anti-patriarchal or post-patriarchal. Another significant assumption arising from the literal interpretation is that patriarchal relations are merely familial relations (23). This assumption allows political debate to ignore patriarchy because of the separation of the private and public spheres in modern civil society. Thus, when it comes to political debate between liberals and socialists, “Patriarchal domination lies outside their frame of reference, along with questions about the relation between the marriage contract and employment contract and any hint that the employment contract, too, is part of the structure of patriarchy” (13). The third assumption, that patriarchy is a universal feature of human society (23), implies a certain ahistoricism and fixity that obscures “the historical distinctiveness of the modern civil order” as well as modern patriarchy’s integral role in capitalism (30); patriarchy is instead seen as a “feudal relic or a remnant of the old world of status that sets the familial, paternal, natural, private sphere apart from the conventional, civil, public world of contract and capitalism” (23).

By pointing out these assumptions in the understanding of patriarchy, Pateman not only shows their interconnectedness to one another, but she also draws attention to how they allow socialists and feminists to join hands with proponents of contract and miss the subordination inherent to it. Integral to this joining and misinterpretation is the notion that “every man has a property in his own Person” (13), an idea put forward by John Locke, which becomes seemingly universalized to every “individual” in the form of contract doctrine put forward by Hobbes and other contractarians (14). As such, Pateman notes that “[t]he subject of all the contracts with which [she] is concerned is a very special kind of property, the property that individuals are held to own in their persons” (5). This notion of property in the person allows socialists and feminists to focus on exploitation rather than subordination, even though, according to Pateman, contracts about property in the person create a relation of subordination by placing the “right of command in the hands of one party to the contract” (8).

In other words, while socialist and feminist critiques recognize that contracts are often entered into on unequal terms that facilitate exploitation, they have not recognized that contracts necessarily render one party dominant and one subordinate. This critique of socialist and feminist analyses is perhaps where Pateman’s stance as a radical feminist is clearest. Pateman sees sexed subordination as civil society’s organizing principle, flipping the socialist argument that gender inequality arises from economic relationships and outright rejecting the liberal tradition as inherently oppressive.

The character of modern patriarchy and the relation of subordination created through contract only become clear when the sexual contract is brought into view as integral to the original contract. As Pateman argues, “Modern civil society is not structured by kinship and the power of fathers; in the modern world, women are subordinated to men as men, or to men as a fraternity. The original contract takes place after the political defeat of the father and creates modern fraternal patriarchy” (3). This fraternal patriarchy surfaces in the classic contract texts that hold that differences in rationality follow from natural sexual difference (5), thus viewing sexual difference as political difference (6). In other words, “what it is to be ‘man’ or ‘woman,’ and the construction of sexual difference as political difference, is central to civil society” (16), and only men, who pass through both private and public spheres, are the “individuals” to whom civil freedom is granted. This implies that fraternal patriarchy is the binding ingredient between the private and public spheres, which gives rise to questions about the relationships between actual contracts in both spheres, especially those involving women. Drawing Chapter 2 to a close, Pateman makes her trajectory for the rest of the book clear:

To understand modern patriarchy, including capitalist economic relations, it is necessary to keep the contract between master and servant or master and slave firmly in mind, and to consider the connection between ‘personalized’ contract in the domestic sphere and contract in the ‘impersonal,’ public world of capitalism (37).

She intends to do so by demonstrating that the sexual contract reveals that all of civil society, not just private relations, have a patriarchal structure, and that this structure masks relations of domination and subordination as relations that preserve equality and freedom through contract and the idea of property in the person.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text