53 pages • 1 hour read
Michael SchurA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Schur presents How to Be Perfect as a kind of guidebook to ethical decision-making. To that end, he summarizes and synthesizes the work of multiple noted philosophers, showing how each makes a valuable and useful contribution to ethical theory. In fact, he structures the text to emphasize the way that each system of moral philosophy fills gaps or adds nuance to the others, suggesting that a holistic, pragmatic approach is superior to adopting any single philosophical system as definitive.
At first, as Schur introduces the major schools of moral philosophy, he devotes a chapter each to virtue ethics, utilitarianism, and deontology, showing the advantages and limitations of each. As he proceeds, touching on the work of dozens of additional philosophers along the way, it becomes clear that Schur is not interested in semantic debates. For instance, he more or less glosses over the fundamental contradiction between utilitarianism, which judges morality solely by results, and deontology, which sees actions themselves as being right or wrong, regardless of their consequences. Instead of trying to resolve this conundrum in favor of one or the other, Schur simply cherry picks his way through philosophy, applying various theories as they suit the question at hand. While philosophy is often associated with intricate debates of minutiae, Schur offers a fresh, alternative approach to philosophical application in one’s everyday life.
This generalization may seem like a dodge or cop-out from Schur, but the book’s later chapters in particular lend legitimacy to his approach in a few key ways. First, Schur’s discussion of William James’s pragmatism, including the thought experiment of the squirrel in the tree, questions whether or not it matters how we describe a moral question or theory as long as it takes us to the right conclusion in the end (this is, in its way, a rather utilitarian outlook); a section heading notably describes this approach as “A Philosophical Jambalaya” (124); the name “jambalaya” refers to the fact that the Cajun dish consists of a wide variety of ingredients jumbled up together. Second, Schur’s inclusion of some existential philosophy questions the very assumption that it is even possible to draw objective conclusions about the nature of morality in a universe where existence is absurd. Instead of worrying so much about unknowable and unresolvable details, Schur suggests that it is best to move forward and choose to live well in spite of uncertainty.
In the Coda, Schur summarizes this theme with some parting advice for his children: “Use the [philosophies] you like, the ones that make sense to you, but keep the others around just in case” (257). Overall, Schur’s text models such a pluralist approach, showing how to navigate the tensions and contradictions between various approaches with grace and humility. While no single system holds full and exclusive access to moral perfection, taken together, they offer more than enough substance for the ethical journey of a lifetime.
With its title, How to Be Perfect: The Correct Answer to Every Moral Question, Schur’s book hovers between philosophical exploration and self-help guidebook: Much of the text is devoted to exploring the mechanics of personal moral development, particularly in the context of Schur’s own moral journey.
Throughout the text, Schur shares several anecdotes from his own life to demonstrate the process of moral awakening and development. Schur traces the genesis of his interest in moral philosophy to an experience he and his wife shared in which they publicly shamed a driver for requesting money to perform aesthetic repairs to his vehicle while rescue efforts were underway in hurricane-stricken New Orleans. Schur describes a pivotal moment when he and his wife both began to feel uneasy. As he puts it, “The little voices in our heads were chirping at us, and we finally started listening to them” (132). From the conversations that followed, Schur developed an interest in moral philosophy, which he began to research. From these experiences, Schur concluded that most moral journeys begin with questions, and perhaps feelings of discomfort, and such journeys are accelerated through conversations with like-minded individuals.
Schur highlights a few other points of interest in his ongoing development. These include his realization that he was desperate to be recognized for his good acts, even the simple act of tipping a barista. This, in turn, spurred Schur to create The Good Place, which constitutes a culmination (thus far) of Schur’s interest in moral philosophy. At the same time, Schur became increasingly aware of the many favorable circumstances and lucky turns that enabled him to succeed, leaving him to wonder about his moral responsibilities to help others. Taken together, these incidents illustrate the need for self-awareness when it comes to effective moral reasoning. To learn from the past, it is sometimes necessary to pause and reflect. By incorporating philosophical theories into his life, Schur was able to put words to innate feelings and poor circumstances and was better able to navigate morality in today’s world.
Schur also addresses failure as an inevitable part of any struggle to change for the better. After describing his own resistance to switching banks despite moral concerns, Schur distinguishes between two types of failure:
[W]e can now be a bit more precise when we define which kinds of failure are good and bad. The good kind comes from trying to do something good, and either miscalculating or just flatly making the wrong decision. That’s the kind of failure that’s 100 percent guaranteed, and 100 percent forgivable—plus the attempt at virtue that led to it lets us learn from what we did, and gives us a better chance at success in the future. The kind I was gesturing at when I didn’t want to change banks came partly from apathy, or maybe ‘moral laziness.’ I didn’t do something I knew would be a little better than the thing I was doing because, well, it was hard and annoying (162).
In the end, it is this laziness and complacency that Schur seeks to dispel in readers. The key to self-improvement is simply to start, and to keep at it, despite inevitable mistakes. Through self-awareness, reflection, interactions with others, and sheer effort, Schur demonstrates that it is possible to make incremental and lasting progress.
Drawing on the theme of Aristotle’s golden mean, Schur repeatedly investigates the tension between meeting others’ needs and caring for the self, seeking to determine the appropriate balance between the two. This is relevant not only in everyday life but also in the comparison and analysis of philosophical perspectives, which often contradict one another and emphasize varying degrees of this balance.
On the one hand, Schur presents several cases of individuals acting in excessive self-interest, to the detriment of others. From his own life, Schur mentions a time that his use of whataboutism left him feeling disappointed in himself. Philosophically, Schur cites Ayn Rand’s system of objectivism as an example of a morally bankrupt system since it denies that the self has any responsibility to the other. Socially, Schur draws attention to those who resisted efforts to wear masks during the COVID-19 pandemic as lacking basic concern for others. Similarly, he presents Ted Yoho’s self-serving, hollow apology to Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez as an example of despicable selfishness. Even charitable figures like Bill Gates are not above criticism, as Schur references Singer’s argument that the wealthy can and should give much more to relief efforts. Overall, examples of selfishness are not exactly rare, nor is Schur’s concept a particularly novel one.
However, Schur begins to push back against conventional wisdom as he questions pre-existing notions of perfection as something akin to moral sainthood. One of his critiques of utilitarianism centers on the possibility for adherents to sacrifice themselves for others, as in the case of the electrician in the thought experiment, whose suffering is allowed to continue so as to not interrupt a sports broadcast. In addition to the moral dubiousness of this approach, Schur suggests that those who are wholly devoted to helping others risk losing their individuality and personality, becoming bland in their determination not to offend others. This in turn contradicts the second formulation of Kant’s categorial imperative, which states that people should never be used as a means to an end.
The challenge, then, is locating the appropriate balance between attending to self-care and helping others. Central to Schur’s argument is his Aristotle-inspired insistence that, however difficult it may be to specify, such a balance does exist and is discoverable through careful reflection. As a general rule, Schur reminds readers that those who are able should probably be giving more than they do. His expressed admiration for ubuntu implies that most people in Western civilization are probably far too stingy when it comes to helping others. Schur, however, also considers a personal example of the time he purchased an autographed baseball bat he purchased for his son. At the time, Schur felt a twinge of discomfort at the realization that he could have spent the money on charity. However, Schur ultimately concludes that he does not regret the purchase since it has meaningfully enriched his life and that of his son. In the end, therefore, there is no easy formula or clear line showing how selfish is too selfish or how generous is too generous.