logo

53 pages 1 hour read

Michael Schur

How to Be Perfect: The Correct Answer to Every Moral Question

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 2022

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Part 2, Chapters 5-8Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Part 2: “In Which We Take Everything We’ve Learned, and We Start Asking Some Tougher Questions, and We Use the Stuff We’ve Learned to Try to Answer Them, and We Also Learn a Bunch More Cool Stuff”

Part 2, Chapter 5 Summary: “Should I Run Into a Burning Building and Try to Save Everyone Trapped Inside?”

Schur opens with the story of Jack Lucas, an American soldier who miraculously survived after shielding his peers from a grenade during World War II. He proceeds to question how good people are required to be, even up to the point of heroic perfection.

To further explore this issue, Schur considers whether it is morally necessary to run into a burning building to try to save the people inside. From a Kantian perspective, we may be required to enter the building, or we may merely send for professional help, depending on which universal maxim we apply to the situation. From a utilitarian perspective, it seems worthwhile to attempt to save multiple lives. However, this reveals another drawback of utilitarianism: the so-called “happiness pump,” which is a person who feels morally compelled to give up everything they have to make others happy. Schur links this with the idea of moral sainthood, as expounded by American philosopher Susan Wolf. According to Wolf, a person who is wholly devoted to serving those in need would miss many personal pursuits, such as art, sports, and hobbies, and risk becoming bland.

Schur suggests that virtue ethics provides a better response to this question. Instead of trying to develop any particular quality, such as bravery or charity, to the extreme, we should try to find the right balance between virtue and vice: A certain amount of impatience, for example, can help a person get things done.

To further this point, Schur describes a thought experiment by American philosopher Judith Jarvis Thomson: Suppose a person is kidnapped and medically connected to a world-famous violinist because she possesses the only pair of compatible kidneys necessary to keep the violinist alive. Kant would argue that the kidnappers are wrong to use the woman as a means to an end, while Aristotle might suggest that the woman cannot truly flourish as long as her freedom is restricted and that, in this case, some selfishness could be beneficial.

Schur concludes by suggesting that we are probably not required to run into burning buildings to save people, but we could also justify doing so from the perspective of any of the three major schools of thought, depending on various nuances.

Part 2, Chapter 6 Summary: “I Just Did Something Unselfish. But What’s in It for Me?!”

One day, Schur realized that he had a habit of waiting until the barista was watching before dropping his change into the tip jar after ordering his daily cup of coffee. The self-reflection that followed eventually led Schur to create a sitcom, The Good Place, set in an imaginary afterlife where people are rewarded according to the kind of life they lived.

Schur links his experience with tipping the barista to the concept of moral desert, which is the notion that people should be rewarded according to the good or bad they do. Like Schur, most people crave recognition for the good they do. To question this impulse, Schur quotes Vietnamese monk Thich Nhat Hanh, who describes the value of mindfulness, or living in the moment without expectation of reward. By looking for a reaction from the barista, Schur was not being mindful. Instead, he was using the act of tipping selfishly, to win praise.

Kant, Schur suggests, would likely disapprove of Schur’s attention-seeking tips, while a utilitarian might approve since seeing the tip can provide happiness to both Schur and the barista. Aristotle, meanwhile, might attribute Schur’s actions to excessive pride or dutifulness since tipping is a social custom.

Returning to a utilitarian perspective, Schur considers the issue of charitable donations, which can be given publicly or anonymously. He reasons that giving a donation publicly may inspire others to follow suit. In Schur’s view, the act of giving is more important than the motivations for doing so. As an example, he recalls a charity event that was hosted by a Hollywood mogul one year and then by that mogul’s rival the next, as a successful ploy to get the latter to raise more than the former.

Although some ethicists consider motivation to be important in evaluating behavior, Schur favors a more pragmatic approach. He cites a thought experiment by American philosopher and psychologist William James: James describes an observer moving around a tree attempting to spot a squirrel, even as the squirrel moves at the same time, staying opposite the observer on the tree. The question is whether the observer walked around the squirrel or not: While he did complete a full circle around the tree, he was always facing the front of the squirrel. James asks whether it really matters and suggests that the debate is a semantic one. In much the same way, instead of worrying too much about underlying principles, a pragmatist focuses on results and outcomes, taking whatever is useful from a variety of different philosophies.

Schur admits that there are limits on acceptable motivations for charitable acts, citing the case of Jeffrey Epstein, who donated money to build up his reputation while committing various crimes. He also warns that those who seek their own happiness are better off following a mindful course than seeking external validation.

Part 2, Chapter 7 Summary: “Yes, I Bumped Into Your Car. But Do You Even Care About Hurricane Katrina?!”

In 2005, Schur’s then-fiancée bumped into another car in slow-moving traffic. At the time, they did not report any damage, but a few days later, the owner of the car requested $836 to replace the fender. Examining the car, Schur saw only a slight mark. Irritated, he offered to donate $836 to relief efforts following the devastation caused by Hurricane Katrina in the man’s name if he would leave his car as is. The man said he would consider Schur’s offer. Schur went on to share the story with friends and family, as well as online, where he won $20,000 in pledges to donate on the condition that the man would agree to void his request for repairs.

Around this time, Schur and his fiancée began to feel bad about what they were doing, though they weren’t sure why. After consulting resources on ethics, Schur realized that he was shaming the owner of the car, who hadn’t really done anything wrong. Schur apologized to the man, sent him the check, and encouraged those who had pledged to donate anyway.

From this experience, Schur learned the difference between shame, which involves public humiliation, and guilt, which involves disappointment in oneself. Schur identifies his treatment of the car owner as an instance of “whataboutism,” or responding to a difficult question or situation by changing the subject instead of responding to the original situation. While shaming can perhaps be useful in some circumstances, Schur’s response far exceeded the demands of the situation.

Schur reviews the incident through various philosophical lenses. From a utilitarian perspective, Schur’s behavior did lead to an increase in charitable donations, but it also set a bad precedent for handling similar situations in the future, potentially causing some anxiety. Kant, meanwhile, would likely disapprove on the grounds that Schur’s behavior violated universal principles while using the car owner as a means to an end. Aristotle would likely see Schur’s behavior as excessive but applaud his self-awareness in recognizing his mistake afterward.

Schur concludes by suggesting that guilt is more likely to lead to change than shame is. Schur adds that the incident served as a major turning point in his moral development.

Part 2, Chapter 8 Summary: “We’ve Done Some Good Deeds, and Given a Bunch of Money to Charity, and We’re Generally Really Nice and Morally Upstanding People, So Can We Take Three of These Free Cheese Samples From the Free Cheese Sample Plate at the Supermarket Even Though It Clearly Says ‘One Per Customer’?”

Schur recalls his father, a music collector, joking that because he didn’t buy any U2 albums, he could spend the equivalent amount of money on other music for free. Schur compares this to moral philosophy, with some people believing that they can build up moral currency by doing good things and then justify doing a few other bad things.

Schur recalls a time when he came to the conclusion that the owners of the bank he frequented were “monsters,” socially and politically speaking. Knowing how much of a hassle it would be to switch banks, Schur was tempted not to make the change due to a condition he calls “moral exhaustion”: Each of us is overwhelmed with choices each day, many of which have ethical dimensions. For instance, Schur’s normally well-behaved dog becomes aggressive and unpleasant whenever he is on a leash, tempting Schur to walk him without a leash from time to time.

Schur suggests that it’s probably okay to break some rules under certain conditions, such as jaywalking on a hot day when there is no traffic. Doing so is allowable as long as we don’t harm others and recognize that our choice is not ideal. Such recognition is critical because, over time, small indiscretions can condition us to commit larger and larger infractions. Schur compares this process to the public policy concept of the Overton window, which shows how ideas once viewed as extreme gradually become acceptable over time. As a case in point, Schur refers to the work of American novelist and philosopher Ayn Rand. In a philosophy she called “objectivism,” Rand proposed that individual self-interest is the ideal basis for a rational life. Schur dismisses objectivism as failing to meet basic ethical standards from utilitarian, Kantian, or Aristotelian perspectives.

Schur introduces another thought experiment known as the free rider problem: As a trolley full of paying passengers sets off down the track, a woman who has not paid jumps onto the outside, hanging onto a pole, to take a free ride. From a Kantian perspective, the woman’s action is wrong, but a utilitarian might accept her choice since it increases happiness, as long as the passengers inside either don’t notice her or don’t care. More important than what they think, Schur suggests, is what the free rider thinks of herself, which may determine whether she makes a habit of breaking rules.

While it can be difficult to differentiate between harmless rule breaking and the kind that leads to more serious outcomes over time, Schur suggests we should pay attention to our guilt and try to learn from it. Referring to the issue of mask wearing during the COVID-19 pandemic, Schur suggests that wearing a mask was a small price to pay for a large social benefit, an example of the social responsibility exemplified by Scanlon’s contractualism.

Schur reveals that he did, eventually, summon the energy to make a difficult but worthwhile change to a bank that was more in line with his values. He suggests that failure to try due to laziness is far worse than mistakes made in ignorance, which are learning opportunities.

Part 2, Chapters 5-8 Analysis

Structurally, this section features a transition from Part 1 to Part 2. While Part 1 is devoted primarily to introducing theories that serve as points of reference, Part 2 takes a more problem-oriented approach, with each chapter addressing a complex situation; Schur applies various philosophical approaches as needed. The book’s parts, like its chapters, are humorously labeled. Unlike the chapter titles, however, the part titles are not questions but rather seemingly random ramblings in Schur’s characteristically casual tone: The title of Part 2 ends with the phrase, “We Also Learn a Bunch More Cool Stuff” (99). Overall, Schur’s structure is designed to help readers feel comfortable tackling sometimes murky philosophical subjects while giving them a roadmap for the text’s trajectory.

Logically, these chapters continue to build on the insights developed previously. An examination of his argument reveals a continuous thread from section to section, and each chapter typically ends with a preview of what comes next. The chapters in Part 2 each deal with the potential for seemingly good actions to be used or interpreted in ways that are counterproductive, whether due to excessive self-sacrifice, tainted motives, whataboutism, or sheer exhaustion.

The Value of a Multifaceted Approach to Ethical Decision-Making remains a central focus. Schur’s conclusion, to him as a pragmatist, is that motivation is not that important in the end. This is noted as a point of agreement with utilitarians, despite Schur’s concerns acknowledged earlier. Here and throughout, Schur’s balanced approach of applying multiple philosophical lenses to each problem serves as a model for readers, reinforcing the need to consider each problem from multiple angles to best understand it. At the same time, as the thought experiment involving the squirrel moving around the tree demonstrates, it may not be worth splitting hairs over semantic details. Ethical decision-making involves making actual decisions, not getting bogged down in endless minutiae.

This section also sees Schur deepen his exploration of Balancing Self-Care With Concern for Others. On the one hand, he describes several incidents or philosophies that demonstrate a dangerous lack of compassion, including the philosophies of Ayn Rand, his own use of whataboutism, and the criminal activities of Jeffrey Epstein. On the other, Schur’s analysis of the burning building and violinist problems acknowledge reasonable limits on self-sacrifice; Schur also highlights situations where it may be appropriate to break small rules or take a metaphorical free ride due to moral exhaustion from time to time. His overall point seems to be that we should probably be more considerate of others than we are, but not to the point of becoming a so-called “happiness pump.” In this way, Schur pushes back against readers’ potentially naïve or idealistic outlooks and expectations about perfection as constituting total denial of the selfish feelings and behaviors.

Schur also weaves several tips and insights about The Process of Personal Development into these chapters. His recollection of his social media crusade against the driver who asked for money to repair his car gives way to a realization that guilt, not public shame, is most likely to inspire change. In fact, Schur’s reflection on his past experiences and acknowledgement of his own guilt about what he did models such change for readers. Schur also presents his unpleasant but successful process of changing banks as an example of the possibility of personal change through concerted effort. Though Schur does not present himself as being anywhere near perfect, his willingness to expose his vulnerabilities as well as celebrate his successes offers readers a chance to look for similar struggles and victories in their own lives.

This section also sees Schur’s authorly persona continue to develop through his stylistic choices. A notable highlight includes perhaps the longest footnote in the book, which is attached to his discussion of the squirrel-in-the-tree thought experiment. In the footnote, Schur explains the social and scientific context of Williams James’s commentary, linking it to revolutionary scientific discoveries. Schur’s decision to feature this information in a footnote demonstrates both his curiosity and passion for the subject matter as well as his respect for readers who may not want to take a semi-lengthy tangent. Schur’s humor also takes on an edge as needed in this section, not only in his critique of Ayn Rand but also in his takedown of a contemporary politician: “A daily perusal of American newspapers reveals dozens of shame-worthy activities: corruption, rampant hypocrisy, using power for personal enrichment, dereliction of duty, racism, dishonesty—and that’s just Ted Cruz!” (134).

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text