logo

37 pages 1 hour read

Jean-Jacques Rousseau

Discourse on the Origin of Inequality

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1755

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Part 1, Pages 106-113Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Part 1, Pages 106-113 Summary

Rousseau begins his description of humankind’s state of nature with the assumption that the physical human form was essentially the same as it is today. The primary difference is that contemporary humans have developed a host of tools for achieving mastery over nature: they build shelter and wear clothing to reduce the impact of weather, create industries to enjoy new goods, and invent medicines to reduce the risks of illness and death. Rousseau’s hypothetical human beings have none of these skills, nor the imagination to develop them. With only their physical assets and an instinct for survival, they accommodate themselves to their environment and seek only to fulfill basic needs.

Overall, the human body is well suited for a life led according to nature. As omnivores, human beings can nourish themselves more easily than many other animals, and the human body adapts well to the challenges of its surroundings. Rousseau believes that “the savage man,” as he calls this hypothetical person, has strength and skills far beyond those of contemporary humans, who have grown reliant on tools, machines, and animals to do much of their work. The modern person is more productive, but the “savage person” has the advantage of being self-sufficient. (Rousseau uses the terms “savage” and “civilized” in their etymological senses to refer to people who live in forests and towns, respectively. This use does not imply that the civilized condition is better. On the contrary, “savages” are happier and morally better in his theory.)

Rousseau then directly challenges the state of nature that Hobbes presents in his book Leviathan (1651), which depicts a struggle for supremacy where human beings relentlessly prey upon one another. Rousseau counters that a natural human being would only find unfamiliar things threatening, and due to their intimate familiarity with their environment, there would be few causes for worry. Should an unforeseen threat arrive, they would be more likely to run away than to act aggressively. Human beings in the state of nature would in many respects be safer and better off than they are in society. No wild animals regularly prey upon humans, and self-sufficient people would have no reason to harm one another. Humans can carry their young more easily than many other animals can, and as capacities diminish in old age, so do appetites, and so the old will gradually die without excessive discomfort. Rousseau then claims that even without access to medicine, human beings in nature would generally be healthier than their civilized counterparts. He attributes most illnesses to modern conditions that allow people to be idle, gluttonous, or anxious as they struggle to balance all the responsibilities of modern life. Medicine only became necessary after the formation of societies gave people so much more cause to be sick. In this regard, the condition of the savage may be “preferable to ours” (111).

In sum, if human beings lived as animals do, nature would have taken good care of them. It was only by trying to surpass other animals that human beings made themselves dependent on machines and other human beings. The first person who fashioned clothing or built a shelter was doing something unnecessary since their ancestors managed to survive without them. With an exclusive concern for self-preservation, a human being’s instincts would have been razor-sharp, as reports of Indigenous people in the Americas in Rousseau’s time conveyed that they could see farther than spyglasses and smell as well as hounds.

Part 1, Pages 106-113 Analysis

Most philosophy on Understanding Human Nature assumes a fundamental difference between humans and other animals. The distinction seems obvious, especially when humans have advanced sufficiently to undertake abstract theorizing on the universe. A society capable of philosophizing has almost certainly built settled communities, possibly even cities, along with an intricate web of political, social, and familial institutions, and has also made extensive use of animals for work, food, and companionship. The ability to philosophize seems to epitomize a fundamental difference: humans enjoy the capability to reason while animals are driven by instinct. Consequently, philosophers who have imagined a “state of nature” may strip away the comforts and institutions of modern society, but they assume human beings in nature would still retain their powers of reason and would therefore be distinct from other creatures.

Rousseau’s Discourse on Inequality takes the radical step of discarding any meaningful difference between humans and other animals. He assumes that a genuine state of nature cannot admit any capacities beyond instinct. Otherwise, human beings would exist above nature from the moment of their first appearance, and while this matches the account from the Bible, it does not suit Rousseau’s purpose of reconstructing human nature based on reason. This leads Rousseau to define a state of nature by taking away not only social conventions but also every capability that humans gain through culture and socialization, such as producing clothing, shelter, and food. Furthermore, these human beings are alone and constantly on the move, eschewing any but the most episodic and transactional relationships. There is ample reason to question this description on empirical grounds. All available evidence of proto-human species suggests some degree of sociability. Even before such discoveries were made, Rousseau could find ample evidence of animals who communicate with one another, form family groups around particular territories, or operate in packs.

Modern language still considers animals inferior to humans, so being forced “to live like an animal” implies both physical deprivation and a blow to their dignity. By depicting humans in an animal-like state, Rousseau subverts the expectations of his readers showing that such people are in many respects better off than their modern counterparts. The modern worker who cannot afford groceries or rent might envy someone who easily acquires food and shelter from their immediate environment. Moreover, the endless social demand to fit an arbitrary standard of attractiveness would vanish in a world where people spent little time around each other. Rousseau may overstate the natural human being’s immunity from illness, but a world still reeling from a pandemic may look longingly on a time when pathogens couldn’t travel across long distances or infect large communities. If Rousseau can convince his audience that human beings could live as solitary animals, and would benefit from doing so in many critical respects, then they are ready for his broader conclusion. There is no natural basis for society and thus no natural basis for inequality. The formation of society amounts to a deterioration in the human condition. Rousseau argues that people have become domesticated and dependent, lacking the vigor that they would have in nature. The example of human beings is even more shameful than that of animals since animals were forced into domestication, while humans did it to themselves.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text