logo

35 pages 1 hour read

Friedrich Nietzsche

Beyond Good And Evil

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1886

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapters 7-9Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Chapter 7 Summary: “Our Virtues”

If the Europeans are to have virtue, it must of course be the virtue that they have found on their own, and it must align with the inclinations and tendencies of the heart. The inclinations must be those of instinct, “the most intelligent of all kinds of intelligence” (131), much more than any other kind of intelligence that has thus been uncovered and related up to the present time. These inclinations are out of favor with the commonfolk, however, and it is their practice to be always judging and condemning the morals of others, always a favorite pastime of those who are intellectually inferior and who wield their superiority as a weapon out of shame for their natural deficiencies.

To the contrary, it is always the interests and concerns of those of a higher constitution and more noble bearing that the commonfolk find boring and completely uninteresting. In the free spirit, the one who is destined to be in command, the virtues of the commoners will needfully be vices, for these virtues would simply be wasted. Sympathy as well, all too fine for the average person, is to be derided, and it is in fact what should truly be held sympathetically. Sympathy is like a religion in contemporary society when in fact it is scorn that must more often be held for others. It is scorn and sympathy for sympathy that is necessary, and “we see how man dwarfs himself” (138), so it is these sympathizers who must be sympathized most, or rather held in contempt.

It is necessary the human race suffer and bleed; misery is necessary, for every greatness and every advancement and every great depth is born from the crucible of suffering. The human person is both “creature and creator” (138), and it is the individual who must suffer in themselves to be fashioned into a new creature. Human beings are meant to suffer.

Nietzsche then provides one of his many commentaries on gender: As to individual human beings, something small is to be said about women, but let it be known right away “at the outset how literally they are merely—MY truths” (145). In contemporary society, women are beginning to assert themselves and enlighten men as to who they are; however, it seems very clear to Nietzsche that there are certain fundamental truths about them. In the first place, there is in women “much pedantry, superficiality” (148), as is seen especially in the manner in which they interact with children. Further, the author asserts, it is for women to be hostile to the truth, but this is to her credit, for men “honor and love this very art and this very instinct in woman” (148) because it makes the man seem foolish and turns the hard seriousness of life into follies, which the man secretly desires and enjoys. It cannot be denied, in the end, that the current democratic regime is one in which women are treated with great respect—but, says Nietzsche, it is also true that there are those who would injudiciously force and encourage women to make themselves masculine, losing what is unique about themselves and imitating all that is “stupid” in men. Against this it can be said that women are feared as they are respected and that “her nature, which is more ‘natural’ than that of man” (152), is one that is revered.

Chapter 8 Summary: “Peoples and Countries”

Listening to Wagner’s Mastersinger engendered a wonder for German music that has not been surpassed in centuries; in the music, it is “the joy of the artist in himself, which he refuses to conceal” (155) that overflows to the listener. The various nations of Europe and their citizens all have unique qualities and of course their own proper vices. On the other hand is the reality that there is simultaneously the emergence of a supra-nationalism, in which the European citizen (regardless of their nationality) is developing similar qualities everywhere; they are “very handy workmen who require a master, a commander” (159). In this situation, the free-spirited strongman will be able to see their power grow even greater than ever before. This situation in which the few who are strong will be able to grow and develop at the expense of the weak and listless masses is one that will eventually breed tyrants.

Uniquely, the German soul possesses hidden depths that nevertheless hold a mysterious chaos; one of the unique German qualities is the quality of “becoming” and it is a “development” that can be considered unique to Germany in itself (160). Nevertheless, the good old days—especially in regard to German musical talent and genius—are at an end, and in fact German music is now an isolated and purely national affair, unable to inspire the greater parts of Europe as a whole. It is not, and has not been for some time, the German word—spoken, preached, and read—that has taken its place at the top of the hierarchy. In fact, the greatest preacher Germany has ever seen, Martin Luther, is also the author of the greatest literary work of German as well, as “the Bible has hitherto been the best German book” (166).

It is in fact the Jews who are the strongest and toughest people, having within themselves the strength to persevere in a slowly declining Europe. It is the Jews and the Russians who will have the greatest part to play over the next century in regard to international politics since Europe is “really rather a res facta than nata” (169), having to be refashioned and molded rather than brought about naturally. The English, on the other hand, are certainly not philosophical but rather attack philosophy generally while France represents what is most refined and intellectual among the European sister states.

That being said, France is on the decline and has yet only three things to which she lays claim: the capacity for emotion proper to the artist; a superior moralistic culture characterized by plurality; and the ability to synthesize southern and northern sensibilities, especially when it comes to religion and temperament.

Chapter 9 Summary: “What is Noble”

In every society that has elevated some over others there has been an instinctual knowledge of hierarchy, in which some are slaves, and some are masters. At first those societies were dominated by “barbarians in every terrible sense of the word, men of prey, still in possession of unbroken strength of will and desire for power” (182), who would prey upon the weak and the listless and those with a proclivity for subservience. Those societies that came to be dominated by the strong were flickering lights and dimming fires, whose life-force had already been close to being extinguished.

Society deems it good conduct when violence is restrained and when injury is avoided; this occurs only in certain conditions, of course, when all persons are generally counted equal and of similar rank, strength, and honor. But this is not reality, for “life itself is essentially appropriation, injury, conquest of the strange and weak” (182), and life is purely about the will to power. Life is exploitation defined: There is no pure morality, and life is not beholden to it. Life is simply this will, this domination. Many struggle against this truth but it cannot be any different than it is; though most hope for a day in which exploitation is an act and concept of the past, this will never be.

The distinctions of various moral systems and values originates in the class of those in power, and the systems differ according to the nature of these rulers. When those in power are the noble and the high-born, this morality is nothing like what is commonly referred to as a morality of good and bad. Additionally, it was never at first particular deeds or words that could be good or moral or noble, but the persons in themselves who were noble and “meritorious. The persons themselves were the creators and judges of morality. This morality was truly beyond good and evil in that it was a morality whose origin lay in the person as subjective, and thus beyond reproach by any extrinsic force or personage.

The second type of morality, however, is the “slave-morality” where “sympathy, the kind, helping hand, the warm heart, patience, diligence, humility, and friendliness” are considered virtues in the antithesis to the morality of the noble (185). It is essentially a morality obsessed with and defined by its usefulness. Here is found a desire for freedom and equality based in fear and the desire to be happy, whatever that may mean. The morality of the noble, by contrast, “counts intolerance itself among the virtues, under the name of ‘justice’” (191), which is in stark difference to the weak and plastic morality of the commonfolk. It is this second morality that breeds mediocrity and will conquer in the days ahead due to its widespread acceptance and appeal.

The noble know better, however, and understand the desire for hierarchy and instinct toward ranking and governance could never be snuffed from the human heart and habits. These habits and deep-seated desires and customs “cannot be effaced from a man’s soul” (194), and it is impossible that one should entirely escape from their past and their lineage. Even education to this end is nothing but a lie and a deceit that aims to disguise the true nature of an individual; education cannot change the nature or the lineage of a person. The noble person sees their own nobility and accepts it without question, seeking only to find themselves in the company of others who are equally noble and privileged as themselves.

Sympathy is the trait of the weak and the ignoble and love the greatest downfall of this conceit. This sympathy is a deceitful power, even to the point of proposing love as the solution to every problem. This is likely the tragedy of the man Jesus Christ, whose sympathy was profound and who went to his death under the hypnosis of love and who had even invented hell as the everlasting abode of torment for those who refused to love and love him. It is the tragedy of the saint to have pity for the filth of humanity.

Chapters 7-9 Analysis

The definition of virtue is at stake in the first chapter of this section (Chapter 7), and the competing arenas of virtue are those inhabited by the general public and those inhabited by the noble few who appear uninteresting and strange to the average person. The common person spends their time passing judgment on the morals and the actions of others; they are content to remain the pinnacle of virtue in their own minds and on the correct side of right and wrong. The noble, however, realize this is an attitude to be overcome, as it is worthless. In the noble free spirit, it is vice (as it is generally called) that will be virtuous, and common virtues like humility and meekness are merely weaknesses to be overcome and avoided.

Sympathy above all is to be cast aside as a religion of the poor, the weak, and the fearful; those who hold sympathy and compassion in high regard are to be trampled. Sympathy, for Nietzsche, is held in such disregard because it is sympathy that allows the weak individuals to persist in the world. Reality and truth are harsh, and only the strong should survive; sympathy upends this value and contradicts the natural order of things. Nietzsche is adamant that suffering is necessary for the human race to advance into what it is meant to become; suffering is absolutely necessary and attempts to alleviate this suffering (in his worldview) are themselves wicked.

Nietzsche believes this sympathetic outlook is instantiated most of all by women, seen by the author as the paragons of sympathy and love, and they are to be pitied most of all for this reason. In many instances, Nietzsche’s positions could be taken to represent sexist and misogynistic viewpoints, but the reality is likely much more complex than this. In many instances he praises women for representing a foil for the men’s more supposedly ill-advised endeavors, and, he claims, their hostility to the truth serves to set them apart from the average man who is content to accept truth uncritically wherever it comes. Nietzsche’s esteem for women is greatly lacking, and he sees in women a superficiality for which he has no time. To be fair, however, he thinks men who wish to masculinize women even stupider in their attempts to manipulate women into imitating a certain intellectual shortcoming Nietzsche believes is peculiar to men.

In Chapter 8, Nietzsche shifts his focus from the individual to the collective, commenting on nations and peoples in general, as his criticism for Europe is collected here with great force. The greatest German composer of the 19th century in Nietzsche’s eyes is Franz Wagner, and this opinion leads him into a discussion of the various virtues and vices of the nations of Europe. He does levy a criticism of the collective nations of Europe as a whole first, denigrating them for moving toward a certain supra-nationalism that would erase the distinctions between the cultures and eventually meld into a mediocre, blasé force of workers with nothing of their own to offer.

He criticizes the Germans for losing their musical qualities, which he sees to have come to an end, but they are to be commended for their literary and oratory genius, especially in the figure of Martin Luther, the greatest preacher that Germany has ever produced and the author of the greatest German prose composition, the Luther Bible. The Jews are also singled out as of particular hardy stock and are praised for their strength and resilience in the face of persecution and hardship; in fact, it is the Jews and the Russians whom Nietzsche believes to be of great importance in the coming era of politics and international relations (a prophecy that would be fulfilled in the first half of the 20th century and the two world wars).

The French, he says, are possessed of three special qualities even though as a whole they are sliding into a general decline. They have a unique capacity for emotion, a superior moralistic culture, and an ability to synthesize various sensibilities within themselves, a cultural fact that will prove useful in their reception and integration of religious and temperamental sentiments. The English, on the other hand, find no positive evaluation in Nietzsche’s eyes, as they have proved themselves to be utterly unphilosophical and generally antagonistic to the true philosophical spirit of the age.

In the final chapter, the author concerns himself with those whom he dubs the noble, a group of a select few who will be able to harness their free spirits and the will to power over and against the herds of the general public, who lay mired in what he calls a slave mentality. Throughout history there have always been cultures that have been conquered by those who were stronger and more cunning than those whom they subjugate, and this victory will be no different in his eyes. Society deems violence and domination by force as wicked because society at large is weak and fearful, but this is not reality, for the truth of realty in itself is the truth of domination and subjugation; life, in Nietzsche’s terms, is purely about the will to power. With the will to power, there is no morality outside the person, but morality is what the strong and noble do; it is defined by their actions.

In every age morality has been dictated by those in power, and when the weak are in control morality is spoken of in terms of intentions, acts, and thoughts. True morality, as witnessed to by the strong and noble, lives in the very person. This morality is that which lies beyond good and evil and is thus beyond reproach. The noble person is moral by definition and by their very existence. The slave-morality as Nietzsche coins the phrase is defined by weakness and sympathy, guided as it is by a fear of being dominated by another, so charity and love are praised, and violence is cursed. This is also the source of the desire for absolute freedom and equality as well, for if everyone is to be equally free and on level footing, the weak will be able to survive in a world whereby all rights they should perish.

As a final word, Nietzsche singles out the man Jesus Christ as the prime example of all that is wrong with love and sympathy, accusing him of inventing hell as a place for those opposed to him to inhabit on account of their lack of love for him. As Nietzsche sees him, Jesus is a figure completely consumed by the notion of love and sympathy and is for this reason to be pitied and held in contempt, and those who would follow after him—the saints of popular piety—are equally to be despised as those who would dare to have pity on the filth of humanity.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text