logo

41 pages 1 hour read

Edmund Burke

A Philosophical Enquiry Into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1756

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Preface-Part 1Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Preface to the First Edition Summary

Written four years after Edmund Burke finished A Philosophical Enquiry into the Sublime and Beautiful, Burke’s preface to the work by emphasizes that this is an investigation of the concepts of beauty, aesthetics, and the sublime, rather than a comprehensive theory. Burke was frustrated with the philosophers’ tendency to conflate ideas of beauty and the sublime, and he hoped to provide a clear distinction between the two.

In the Preface, Burke sets forth his method for examining the topic: (1) he carefully explores his own experiences with aesthetics, (2) he makes a detailed record of art which inspires his passion, and (3) considers this art within the laws of nature.

Preface to the Second Edition Summary

Burke’s second edition seeks to respond to certain criticisms of his first edition. Although he does not change his stance, the second edition includes more detailed explanations of his ideas. Burke acknowledges that the study of aesthetics is elusive, and he encourages his readers to carry the torch of research and study beyond what he has prepared.

Introduction on Taste Summary

Burke opens with a bold claim: All taste is the same. Burke asserts that all humans have the same relative taste—the same likes and dislikes, the same appreciations for art. Furthermore, this taste can be measured through quantifiable means.

Burke begins by defining taste, although he admits that he finds definitions extremely limiting. He determines that taste is the process of the mind when casting judgement about the arts. All humans are given natural powers: the senses, imagination, and judgement. Burke asserts that all these powers contribute to, and are a part of, taste.

He develops his argument that all humans agree on certain principles of culinary taste. Bitter things, like coffee and beer, taste bitter to all people. Sweet things, like sugar and honey, taste sweet to all people. Whether or not a person likes these tastes is directly related to the item’s association with either pleasure or pain. These two feelings—pleasure and pain—drive taste for all people. While some people develop an affinity for certain things, it is the pleasure they get from their effects that causes them to think they like them.

Burke uses the examples of sourness and bitterness. Although many people profess to like beer or coffee, their appreciation of these beverages is related to the pleasure they receive from their narcotic effects. The only way to distinguish between natural taste and acquired taste is whether a person would describe something pleasant with the descriptor—because no person would delightfully exclaim that something was bitter, Burke asserts that no person has a natural taste for bitterness. The same is true, Burke claims, for visual stimulants. He argues that all humans would find the sight of a summer field more pleasant than the same field in winter. The senses translate information as pleasurable or painful, and taste is developed from these sensations.

Imagination plays a secondary role in taste. Burke explains that the imagination can take any sensory impression and create a variation of it. He argues that no ideas produced by the imagination are entirely new; they must always mimic information that has been received through the senses. The imagination is an internal playground that is directly tied to pain and pleasure: “Now the imagination is the most extensive province of pleasure and pain, as it is the region of our fears and our hopes, and of all our passions that are connected with them” (18). The images created in this way bring pain or pleasure, but Burke suggests there is always pleasure in the formation of an imitation.

Taste remains the same over the course of one’s life, but how one feels about art may change as more knowledge is gained. An artist who looks back on their earlier work and feels embarrassed did not suffer a lack of taste at the beginning—they merely lacked the experience and knowledge to realize their imitation in a more exacting way. Burke sees taste as developing by degrees: All tastes are the same, but as people become educated, their tastes become increasingly refined and deeper. A person’s judgement is an important factor in developing taste. If a person has poor judgement, their taste will inevitably be considered poor.

Part 1 Summary

Consistent with the canon of philosophical writing, Burke opens by defining the terms he will use throughout the work and developing an understanding of the basic principles of his ideas on aesthetics. He outlines the various emotions and processes of thinking that contribute to pleasure, pain, and taste.

Burke identifies curiosity as the most basic function of the human mind. Children are endlessly curious, and novelty is their goal. They seek anything that is new or different. Curiosity causes the individual to fly from one concept to the next, never really landing to discover something in its depth. However, curiosity is central to passion—which forms the basis for all pleasure and pain.

Burke suggests that it is impossible to define pain and pleasure. It is possible, however, to identify different types of pain and pleasure and how they affect the mind. He rejects an earlier belief that pain emerges when pleasure is taken away and that pleasure emerges when pain is taken away. Instead, he suggests that both pain and pleasure are independent of one another. Emotions like delight are predicated upon the removal of pain, but other experiences of pleasure have no ties to pain. All humans experience one of three states at any given moment: indifference, pleasure, or pain. Some modes of pain or pleasure are positive.

Rather than eliciting pain, the absence of pleasure produces three human conditions: indifference, disappointment, and grief. The latter can produce its own type of pleasure: “It is the nature of grief to keep its object perpetually in its eye, to present it in its most pleasurable views, to repeat all the circumstances that attend it, even to the last minuteness; to go back to every particular enjoyment, to dwell upon each, and to find a thousand new perfections in all” (32). Grief invites people into a loop of sadness and pleasure.

Most passions, whether born from pleasure or pain, can be divided into two categories: self-preservation and society. Self-preservation is tied to pain and danger; the individual worries about sickness, death, and safety. Passions for society fall under two headings: sexes and general society. Societal pleasure and pain may be derived from spending time with others or in solitude. Spending time in good company can elicit pleasure just as spending time with bad company can elicit positive pain. The same is true for solitude.

The passions then evolve into three branches: sympathy, imitation, and ambition. Sympathy invites the individual to live inside and understand the experiences of others. Poetry and painting lend themselves to this type of passion. Whereas sympathy derives pleasure from understanding what others feel, imitation derives pleasure from understanding what others do. Ambition keeps artists from feeling satisfied with merely replicating the feelings and experiences of others. Ambition creates space for the individual to distinguish ideas from the ideas of others.

Beauty is a social quality that causes an individual to feel affection and tenderness. Burke separates beauty from lust, although he recognizes the connection between the two. Beauty has a mysteriousness to it that the philosopher suggests may reflect divine wisdom. Burke then introduces the sublime for the first time, which he defines as anything that excites ideas of pain, producing the most powerful emotion.

Preface-Part 1 Analysis

Burke opens his enquiry into the sublime and beautiful by discussing and defining taste. Philosophical works often open by defining ideas that are central to the concepts discussed. To understand aesthetics, Burke establishes a definition for the two aspects of aesthetics that he believes contribute to the quality and feeling of a work: Beauty and the Sublime. Prior to Burke’s work on aesthetics, most ideas about taste were relative to the classical writings of Plato and Aristotle. Plato developed ideas about goodness and beauty, arguing that human representations of art were attempts to achieve the perfection of “Forms”—aspects of a higher realm that cannot be perceived with human senses. Artistic renderings could only hint at the true nature of Divine Forms. Later, Aristotle proposed that beauty is connected to proportion and harmony.

Burke challenges the ideas of both Plato and Aristotle in A Philosophical Enquiry into the Sublime and Beautiful. He argues that beauty is not relative to goodness; in fact, truth and virtue have little to do with beauty at all. Instead, beauty is closely connected to sensory experience. Humans appreciate beauty not because its more perfect form lives in a different realm of understanding; they appreciate beauty because of the pleasure they obtain through their senses. Burke repeatedly rejects the idea that proportion is connected to beauty; even if humans determine specific measurements for an object to be beautiful, Burke argues that imperfections and variations in those measurements often contribute to overall beauty.

However, Burke does adhere to the idea that there are specific tastes that are universal to all people. He points to the development of a person’s literal taste as an example of this. All humans, he claims, agree on the flavors of things that are bitter or sweet. Their appreciation of the nuances of flavors comes with time and experiences of pleasure. Burke cites several instances in which a person’s judgement may be lacking enough to lead them toward bad taste. He admits that it may simply be an intellectual failure, but he also suggests that bad taste is directly related to “ignorance, inattention, prejudice, rashness, levity, obstinacy” (24). Therefore, good taste is developed over time. Beauty represents a base form of appreciation, while the sublime represents a more complex feeling related to the more complex nature of God. The only way to evolve one’s taste is through sensory impression, connected to the theme Aesthetics and Sensory Information.

Burke was highly influenced by the work of John Locke, especially An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, in which Locke explores the origin and development of ideas. During the 18th century, this text formed the foundation of future philosophical inquiry and criticism. Locke overturned the classical notions of Plato and Aristotle by asserting that certain ideas were not a part of an innate knowledge instilled in each person. Instead, Locke proposed that all ideas were formed through sensory experience. While many of Burke’s arguments challenge Locke, he adheres to the importance of the senses in understanding aesthetics. According to Burke, greater understanding requires greater experience. The more sensory impressions a person gains, the more refined their tastes will become.

Burke also claims that all taste is related to pleasure and pain, contributing to the theme The Role of Pleasure and Pain in the Arts. In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (350 BCE), the Greek philosopher suggests pain and pleasure inform virtue: A person knows what is right by the pleasure that is derived from the action. Similarly, a person knows what is wrong because of the pain that is derived. Aristotle emphasizes the importance of finding balance between pain and pleasure. For Burke, pain and pleasure influence taste and passions. The interest that humans take beyond mere curiosity is dependent upon the level of pain or pleasure that the object gives them. Burke envisions pain and pleasure as complex and nuanced concepts that—although not dependent upon one another—often mix and influence one another. Beauty is found when the object elicits pleasure, but the sublime is a more complicated and, therefore, stronger sense. For the sublime, objects elicit pleasure and hint at pain. Burke defines the sublime as those art forms which cause one to feel terror or awe—sublime art is that which hints at darkness.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text